skip to main |
skip to sidebar
The present day attack on statues is not unlike the attack on art, literature, film and history of people who do not live up to the values of 2020. It is like the attack on icons and on human depiction by Christians, Byzantines, and Moslems that went on for hundreds of years. It is a form of iconoclasm. Men held virtually sacred by past and present groups of people are now despised by others.
One of the men I've despised since first learning about him is Andrew Jackson
Nonetheless, I have no desire to deface or destroy his statue. The work is too well crafted, a work of art. It goes with the square and the history of New Orleans. I certainly get it that statues of Confederate generals with little or no aesthetic value, erected in the 1950s or 1960s as political expressions of a refusal to accept integration, should be removed or destroyed (or given to their descendants). But perhaps there are a few with real merit, made in the 19th Century that could remain somewhere with an appropriate plaque and commentary on the person's good and bad points. Do we really want to destroy the sculptures of famous Europeans like Napoleon or Augustus Caesar? And if so, what about the paintings of them, the images of George Washington or Thomas Jefferson? For that matter, don't we want to see the villains as well: Nero, Mussolini, Hitler? After all, don't we all have both good and bad traits? Even those we admire the most have traits that fall short of 21st C. values and attitudes. If we are going to continue to sculpt statues of those we consider heroes, perhaps we could focus on less controversial figures: artists, humanitarians, and the like...Keep the artistic statues in the sculpture sections of our great museums:
Hatshepsut
--Jameson
EXISTENTIALISM
AND HUMAN EMOTIONS
EXISTENTIALISM
I should like on this occasion to defend existentialism against some charges which
have been brought against it.
First, it has been charged with inviting people to remain in a kind of desperate
quietism because, since no solutions are possible, we should have to consider action
in this world as quite impossible. We should then end up in a philosophy of
contemplation; and since contemplation is a luxury, we come in the end to a
bourgeois philosophy. The communists in particular have made these charges.
On the other hand, we have been charged with dwelling on human degradation, with
pointing up everywhere the sordid, shady, and slimy, and neglecting the gracious and
beautiful, the bright side of human nature; for example, according to Mlle. Mercier, a
Catholic critic, with forgetting the smile of the child. Both sides charge us with
having ignored human solidarity, with considering man as an isolated being. The
communists say that the main reason for this is that we take pure subjectivity, the
Cartesian I think, as our starting point; in other words, the moment in which man
becomes fully aware of what it means to him to be an isolated being; as a result, we
are unable to return to a state of solidarity with the men who are not ourselves, a state
which we can never reach in the cogito.
From the Christian standpoint, we are charged with denying the reality and
seriousness of human undertakings, since, if we reject God's commandments and the
eternal verities, there no longer remains anything but pure caprice, with everyone
permitted to do as he pleases and incapable, from his own point of view, of
condemning the points of view and acts of others.
I shall try today to answer these different charges. Many people are going to be
surprised at what is said here about humanism. We shall try to see in what sense it is
to be understood. In any case, what can be said from the very beginning is that by
existentialism we mean a doctrine which makes human life possible and, in addition,
declares that every truth and every action implies a human setting and a human
subjectivity.
As is generally known, the basic charge against us is that we put the emphasis on the
dark side of human life. Someone recently told me of a lady who, when she let slip a
vulgar word in a moment of irritation, excused herself by saying, "I guess I'm
becoming an existentialist." Consequently, existentialism is regarded as something
ugly; that is why we are said to be naturalists; and if we are, it is rather surprising that
in this day and age we cause so much more alarm and scandal than does naturalism,
properly so called. The kind of person who can take in his stride such a novel as
Zola's The Earth is disgusted as soon as he starts reading an existentialist novel; the
kind of person who is resigned to the wisdom of the ages--which is pretty sad--finds
us even sadder. Yet, what can be more disillusioning than saying "true charity begins
at home" or "a scoundrel will always return evil for good"?
We know the commonplace remarks made when this subject comes up, remarks
which always add up to the same thing: we shouldn't struggle against the powers-thatbe; we shouldn't resist, authority; we shouldn't try to rise above our station; any action
which doesn't conform to authority is romantic; any effort not based on past
experience is doomed to failure; experience shows that man's bent is always toward
trouble, that there must be a strong hand to hold him in check, if not, there will be
anarchy. There are still people who go on mumbling these melancholy old saws, the
people who say, "It's only human!" whenever a more or less repugnant act is pointed
out to them, the people who glut themselves on chansons réalistes; these are the
people who accuse existentialism of being too gloomy, and to such an extent that I
wonder whether they are complaining about it, not for its pessimism, but much rather
its optimism. Can it be that what really scares them in the doctrine I shall try to
present here is that it leaves to man a possibility of choice? To answer this question,
we must re-examine it on a strictly philosophical plane. What is meant by the term
existentialism?
Most people who use the word would be rather embarrassed if they had to explain it,
since, now that the word is all the rage, even the work of a musician or painter is
being called existentialist. A gossip columnist in Clartés signs himself The
Existentialist, so that by this time the word has been so stretched and has taken on so
broad a meaning, that it no longer means anything at all. It seems that for want of an
advance-guard doctrine analogous to surrealism, the kind of people who are eager for
scandal and flurry turn to this philosophy which in other respects does not at all serve
their purposes in this sphere.
Actually, it is the least scandalous, the most austere of doctrines. It is intended strictly
for specialists and philosophers. Yet it can be defined easily. What complicates
matters is that there are two kinds of existentialist; first, those who are Christian,
among whom I would include Jaspers and Gabriel Marcel, both Catholic; and on the
other hand the atheistic existentialists, among whom I class Heidegger, and then the
French existentialists and myself. What they have in common is that they think that
existence precedes essence, or, if you prefer, that subjectivity must be the starting
point.
Just what does that mean? Let us consider some object that is manufactured, for
example, a book or a paper-cutter: here is an object which has been made by an
artisan whose inspiration came from a concept. He referred to the concept of what a
paper-cutter is and likewise to a known method of production, which is part of the
concept, something which is, by and large, a routine. Thus, the paper-cutter is at once
an object produced in a certain way and, on the other hand, one having a specific use;
and one can not postulate a man who produces a paper-cutter but does not know what
it is used for. Therefore, let us say that, for the paper-cutter, essence--that is, the
ensemble of both the production routines and the properties which enable it to be both
produced and defined--precedes existence. Thus, the presence of the paper-cutter or
book in front of me is determined. Therefore, we have here a technical view of the
world whereby it can be said that production precedes existence.
When we conceive God as the Creator, He is generally thought of as a superior sort of
artisan. Whatever doctrine we may be considering, whether one like that of Descartes
or that of Leibnitz, we always grant that will more or less follows understanding or, at
the very least, accompanies it, and that when God creates He knows exactly what He
is creating. Thus, the concept of man in the mind of God is comparable to the concept
of paper-cutter in the mind of the manufacturer, and, following certain techniques and
a conception, God produces man, just as the artisan, following a definition and a
technique, makes a paper-cutter. Thus, the individual man is the realization of a
certain concept in the divine intelligence.
In the eighteenth century, the atheism of the philosophes discarded the idea of God,
but not so much for the notion that essence precedes existence. To a certain extent,
this idea is found everywhere; we find it in Diderot, in Voltaire, and even in Kant.
Man has a human nature; this human nature, which is the concept of the human, is
found in all men, which means that each man is a particular example of a universal
concept, man. In Kant, the result of this universality is that the wild-man, the natural
man, as well as the bourgeois, are circumscribed by the same definition and have the
same basic qualities. Thus, here too the essence of man precedes the historical
existence that we find in nature.
Atheistic existentialism, which I represent, is more coherent. It states that if God does
not exist, there is at least one being in whom existence precedes essence, a being who
exists before he can be defined by any concept, and that this being is man, or, as
Heidegger says, human reality. What is meant here by saying that existence precedes
essence? It means that, first of all, man exists, turns up, appears on the scene, and,
only afterwards, defines himself. If man, as the existentialist conceives him, is
indefinable, it is because at first he is nothing. Only afterward will he be something,
and he himself will have made what he will be. Thus, there is no human nature, since
there is no God to conceive it. Not only is man what he conceives himself to be, but
he is also only what he wills himself to be after this thrust toward existence.
Man is nothing else but what he makes of himself. Such is the first principle of
existentialism. It is also what is called subjectivity, the name we are labeled with
when charges are brought against us. But what do we mean by this, if not that man
has a greater dignity than a stone or table? For we mean that man first exists, that is,
that man first of all is the being who hurls himself toward a future and who is
conscious of imagining himself as being in the future. Man is at the start a plan which
is aware of itself, rather than a patch of moss, a piece of garbage, or a cauliflower;
nothing exists prior to this plan; there is nothing in heaven; man will be what he will
have planned to be. Not what he will want to be. Because by the word "will" we
generally mean a conscious decision, which is subsequent to what we have already
made of ourselves. I may want to belong to a political party, write a book, get
married; but all that is only a manifestation of an earlier, more spontaneous choice
that is called "will." But if existence really does precede essence, man is responsible
for what he is. Thus, existentialism's first move is to make every man aware of what
he is and to make the full responsibility of his existence rest on him. And when we
say that a man is responsible for himself, we do not only mean that he is responsible
for his own individuality, but that he is responsible for all men.
The word subjectivism has two meanings, and our opponents play on the two.
Subjectivism means, on the one hand, that an individual chooses and makes himself;
and, on the other that it is impossible for man to transcend human subjectivity. The
second of these is the essential meaning of existentialism. When we say that man
chooses his own self, we mean that every one of us does likewise; but we also mean
by that that in making this choice he also chooses all men. In fact, in creating the man
that we want to be, there is not a single one of our acts which does not at the same
time create an image of man as we think he ought to be. To choose to be this or that is
to affirm at the same time the value of what we choose, because we can never choose
evil. We always choose the good, and nothing can be good for us without being good
for all.
If, on the other hand, existence precedes essence, and if we grant that we exist and
fashion our image at one and the same time, the image is valid for everybody and for
our whole age. Thus, our responsibility is much greater than we might have supposed,
because it involves all mankind. If I am a workingman and choose to join a Christian
trade-union rather than be a communist, and if by being a member I want to show that
the best thing for man is resignation, that the kingdom of man is not of this world, I
am not only involving my own case-I want to be resigned fox everyone. As a result,
my action has involved all humanity. To take a more individual matter, if I want to
marry, to have children; even if this marriage depends solely on my own
circumstances or passion or wish, I am involving all humanity in monogamy and not
merely myself. Therefore, I am responsible for myself and for everyone else. I am
creating a certain image of man of my own choosing. In choosing myself, I choose
man.
This helps us understand what the actual content is of such rather grandiloquent
words as anguish, forlornness, despair. As you will see, it's all quite simple.
First, what is meant by anguish? The existentialists say at once that man is anguish.
What that means is this: the man who involves himself and who realizes that he is not
only the person he chooses to be, but also a lawmaker who is, at the same time,
choosing all mankind as well as himself, can not help escape the feeling of his total
and deep responsibility. Of course, there are many people who are not anxious; but
we claim that they are hiding their anxiety, that they are fleeing from it. Certainly,
many people believe that when they do something, they themselves are the only ones
involved, and when someone says to them, "What if everyone acted that way?" they
shrug their shoulders and answer, "Everyone doesn't act that way." But really, one
should always ask himself, "What would happen if everybody looked at things that
way?" There is no escaping this disturbing thought except by a kind of double-dealing. A man who lies and makes excuses for himself by saying "not everybody
does that," is someone with an uneasy conscience, because the act of lying implies
that a universal value is conferred upon the lie.
Anguish is evident even when it conceals itself. This is the anguish that Kierkegaard
called the anguish of Abraham. You know the story: an angel has ordered Abraham to
sacrifice his son; if it really were an angel who has come and said, "You are
Abraham, you shall sacrifice your son," everything would be all right. But everyone
might first wonder, "Is it really an angel, and am I really Abraham? What proof do I
have?"
There was a madwoman who had hallucinations; someone used to speak to her on the
telephone and give her orders. Her doctor asked her, "Who is it who talks to you?"
She answered, "He says it's God." What proof did she really have that it was God? If
an angel comes to me, what proof is there that it's an angel? And if I hear voices, what
proof is there that they come from heaven and not from hell, or from the
subconscious, or a pathological condition? What proves that they are addressed to
me? What proof is there that I have been appointed to impose my choice and my
conception of man on humanity? I'll never find any proof or sign to convince me of
that. If a voice addresses me, it is always for me to decide that this is the angel's
voice; if I consider that such an act is a good one, it is I who will choose to say that it
is good rather than bad.
Now, I'm not being singled out as an Abraham, and yet at every moment I'm obliged
to perform exemplary acts. For every man, everything happens as if all mankind had
its eyes fixed on him and were guiding itself by what he does. And every man ought
to say to himself, "Am I really the kind of man who has the right to act in such a way
that humanity might guide itself by my actions?" And if he does not say that to
himself, he is masking his anguish.
There is no question here of the kind of anguish which would lead to quietism, to
inaction. It is a matter of a simple sort of anguish that anybody who has had
responsibilities is familiar with. For example, when a military officer takes the
responsibility for an attack and sends a certain number of men to death, he chooses to
do so, and in the main he alone makes the choice. Doubtless, orders come from above,
but they are too broad; he interprets them, and on this interpretation depend the lives
of ten or fourteen or twenty men. In making a decision he can not help having a
certain anguish. All leaders know this anguish. That doesn't keep them from acting;
on the contrary, it is the very condition of their action. For it implies that they
envisage a number of possibilities, and when they choose one, they realize that it has
value only because it is chosen. We shall see that this kind of anguish, which is the
kind that existentialism describes, is explained, in addition, by a direct responsibility
to the other men whom it involves. It is not a curtain separating us from action, but is
part of action itself.
When we speak of forlornness, a term Heidegger was fond of, we mean only that God
does not exist and that we have to face all the consequences of this. The existentialist
is strongly opposed to a certain kind of secular ethics which would like to abolish
God with the least possible expense. About 1880, some French teachers tried to set up
a secular ethics which went something like this: God is a useless and costly
hypothesis; we are discarding it; but, meanwhile, in order for there to be an ethics, a
society, a civilization, it is essential that certain values be taken seriously and that
they be considered as having an a priori existence. It must be obligatory, a priori, to
be honest, not to lie, not to beat your wife, to have children, etc., etc. So we're going
to try a little device which will make it possible to show that values exist all the same,
inscribed in a heaven of ideas, though otherwise God does not exist. In other words--
and this, I believe, is the tendency of everything called reformism in France--nothing
will be changed if God does not exist. We shall find ourselves with the same norms of
honesty, progress, and humanism, and we shall have made of God an outdated
hypothesis which will peacefully die off by itself.
The existentialist, on the contrary, thinks it very distressing that God does not exist,
because all possibility of finding values in a heaven of ideas disappears along with
Him; there can no longer be an a priori Good, since there is no infinite and perfect
consciousness to think it. Nowhere is it written that the Good exists, that we must be
honest, that we must not lie; because the fact is we are on a plane where there are only
men. Dostoievsky said, "If God didn't exist, everything would be possible." That is
the very starting point of existentialism. Indeed, everything is permissible if God does
not exist, and as a result man is forlorn, because neither within him nor without does
he find anything to cling to. He can't start making excuses for himself.
If existence really does precede essence, there is no explaining things away by
reference to a fixed and given human nature. In other words, there is no determinism,
man is free, man is freedom. On the other hand, if God does not exist, we find no
values or commands to turn to which legitimize our conduct. So, in the bright realm
of values, we have no excuse behind us, nor justification before us. We are alone,
with no excuses.
That is the idea I shall try to convey when I say that man is condemned to be free.
Condemned, because he did not create himself, yet, in other respects is free; because,
once thrown into the world, he is responsible for everything he does. The
existentialist does not believe in the power of passion. He will never agree that a
sweeping passion is a ravaging torrent which fatally leads a man to certain acts and is
therefore an excuse. He thinks that man is responsible for his passion.
The existentialist does not think that man is going to help himself by finding in the
world some omen by which to orient himself. Because he thinks that man will
interpret the omen to suit himself. Therefore, he thinks that man, with no support and
no aid, is condemned every moment to invent man. Ponge, in a very fine article, has
said, "Man is the future of man." That's exactly it. But if it is taken to mean that this
future is recorded in heaven, that God sees it, then it is false, because it would really
no longer be a future. If it is taken to mean that, whatever a man may be, there is a
future to be forged, a virgin future before him, then this remark is sound. But then we
are forlorn.
To give you an example which will enable you to understand forlornness better, I
shall cite the case of one of my students who came to see me under the following
circumstances: his father was on bad terms with his mother, and, moreover, was
inclined to be a collaborationist; his older brother had been killed in the German
offensive of 1940, and the young man, with somewhat immature but generous
feelings, wanted to avenge him. His mother lived alone with him, very much upset by
the half-treason of her husband and the death of her older son; the boy was her only
consolation.
The boy was faced with the choice of leaving for England and joining the Free French
Forces--that is, leaving his mother behind or remaining with his mother and helping
her to carry on. He was fully aware that the woman lived only for him and that his
going off--and perhaps his death--would plunge her into despair. He was also aware
that every act that he did for his mother's sake was a sure thing, in the sense that it
was helping her to carry on, whereas every effort he made toward going off and
fighting was an uncertain move which might run aground and prove completely
useless; for example, on his way to England he might, while passing through Spain,
be detained indefinitely in a Spanish camp; he might reach England or Algiers and be
stuck in an office at a desk job. As a result, he was faced with two very different kinds
of action: one, concrete, immediate, but concerning only one individual; the other
concerned an incomparably vaster group, a national collectivity, but for that very
reason was dubious, and might be interrupted en route. And, at the same time, he was
wavering between two kinds of ethics. On the one hand, an ethics of sympathy, of
personal devotion; on the other, a broader ethics, but one whose efficacy was more
dubious. He had to choose between the two.
Who could help him choose? Christian doctrine? No. Christian doctrine says, "Be
charitable, love your neighbor, take the more rugged path, etc., etc." But which is the
more rugged path? Whom should he love as a brother? The fighting man or his
mother? Which does the greater good, the vague act of fighting in a group, or the
concrete one of helping a particular human being to go on living? Who can decide a
priori? Nobody. No book of ethics can tell him. The Kantian ethics says, "Never treat
any person as a means, but as an end." Very well, if I stay with my mother, I'll treat
her as an end and not as a means; but by virtue of this very fact, I'm running the risk
of treating the people around me who are fighting, as means; and, conversely, if I go
to join those who are fighting, I'll be treating them as an end, and, by doing that, I run
the risk of treating my mother as a means.
If values are vague, and if they are always too broad for the concrete and specific case
that we are considering, the only thing left for us is to trust our instincts. That's what
this young man tried to do; and when I saw him, he said, "In the end, feeling is what
counts. I ought to choose whichever pushes me in one direction. If I feel that I love
my mother enough to sacrifice everything else for her--my desire for vengeance, for
action, for adventure--then I'll stay with her. If, on the contrary, I feel that my love for
my mother isn't enough, I'll leave."
But how is the value of a feeling detcrmined? What gives his feeling for his mother
value? Precisely the fact that he remained with her. I may say that I like so-and-so
well enough to sacrifice a certain amount of money for him, but I may say so only if
I've done it. I may say "I love my mother well enough to remain with her" if I have
remained with her. The only way to determine the value of this affection is, precisely,
to perform an act which confirms and defines it. But, since I require this affection to
justify my act, I find myself caught in a vicious circle.
On the other hand, Gide has well said that a mock feeling and a true feeling are
almost indistinguishable; to decide that I love my mother and will remain with her, or
to remain with her by putting on an act, amount somewhat to the same thing: In other
words, the feeling is formed by the acts one performs; so, I can not refer to it in order
to act upon it. Which means that I can neither seek within myself the true condition
which will impel me to act, nor apply to a system of ethics for concepts which will
permit me to act. You will say, "At least, he did go to a teacher for advice." But if you
seek advice from a priest, for example, you have chosen this priest; you already knew,
more or less, just about what advice he was going to give you. In other words,
choosing your adviser is involving yourself. The proof of this is that if you are a
Christian, you will say, "Consult a priest." But some priests are collaborating, some
are just marking time, some are resisting. Which to choose? If the young man chooses
a priest who is resisting or collaborating, he has already decided on the kind of advice
he's going to get. Therefore, in coming to see me he knew the answer I was going to
give him, and I had only one answer to give: "You're free, choose, that is, invent." No
general ethics can show you what is to be done; there are no omens in the world. The
Catholics will reply, ""But there are." Granted--but, in any case, I myself choose the
meaning they have.
When I was a prisoner, I knew a rather remarkable young man who was a Jesuit. He
had entered the Jesuit order in the following way: he had had a number of very bad
breaks; in childhood, his father died, leaving him in poverty, and he was a scholarship
student at a religious institution where he was constantly made to feel that he was
being kept out of charity; then, he failed to get any of the honors and distinctions that
children like; later on, at about eighteen, he bungled a love affair; finally, at twentytwo, he failed in military training, a childish enough matter, but it was the last straw.
This young fellow might well have felt that he had botched everything. It was a sign
of something, but of what? He might have taken refuge in bitterness or despair. But
he very wisely looked upon all this as a sign that he was not made for secular
triumphs, and that only the triumphs of religion, holiness, and faith were open to him.
He saw the hand of God in all this, and so he entered the order. Who can help seeing
that he alone decided what the sign meant?
Some other interpretation might have been drawn from this series of setbacks; for
example, that he might have done better to turn carpenter or revolutionist. Therefore,
he is fully responsible for the interpretation. Forlornness implies that we ourselves
choose our being. Forlornness and anguish go together.
As for despair, the term has a very simple meaning. It means that we shall confine
ourselves to reckoning only with what depends upon our will, or on the ensemble of
probabilities which make our action possible. When we want something, we always
have to reckon with probabilities. I may be counting on the arrival of a friend. The
friend is coming by rail or street-car; this supposes that the train will arrive on
schedule, or that the street-car will not jump the track. I am left in the realm of
possibility; but possibilities are to be reckoned with only to the point where my action
comports with the ensemble of these possibilities, and no further. The moment the
possibilities I am considering are not rigorously involved by my action, I ought to
disengage myself from them, because no God, no scheme, can adapt the world and its
possibilities to my will. When Descartes said, "Conquer yourself rather than the
world," he meant essentially the same thing.
The Marxists to whom I have spoken reply, "You can rely on the support of others in
your action, which obviously has certain limits because you're not going to live
forever. That means: rely on both what others are doing elsewhere to help you, in
China, in Russia, and what they will do later on, after your death, to carry on the
action and lead it to its fulfillment, which will be the revolution. You even have to
rely upon that, otherwise you're immoral." I reply at once that I will always rely on
fellow-fighters insofar as these comrades are involved with me in a common struggle,
in the unity of a party or a group in which I can more or less make my weight felt;
that is, one whose ranks I am in as a fighter and whose movements I am aware of at
every moment. In such a situation, relying on the unity and will of the party is exactly
like counting on the fact that the train will arrive on time or that the car won't jump
the track. But, given that man is free and that there is no human nature for me to
depend on, I can not count on men whom I do not know by relying on human
goodness or man's concern for the good of society. I don't know what will become of
the Russian revolution; I may make an example of it to the extent that at the present
time it is apparent that the proletariat plays a part in Russia that it plays in no other
nation. But I can't swear that this will inevitably lead to a triumph of the proletariat.
I've got to limit myself to what I see.
Given that men are free and that tomorrow they will freely decide what man will be, I
can not be sure that, after my death, fellow-fighters will carry on my work to bring it
to its maximum perfection. Tomorrow, after my death, some men may decide to set
up Fascism, and the others may be cowardly and muddled enough to let them do it.
Fascism will then be the human reality, so much the worse for us.
Actually, things will be as man will have decided they are to be. Does that mean that I
should abandon myself to quietism? No. First, I should involve myself; then, act on
the old saw, "Nothing ventured, nothing gained." Nor does it mean that I shouldn't
belong to a party, but rather that I shall have no illusions and shall do what I can. For
example, suppose I ask myself, "Will socialization, as such, ever come about?" I
know nothing about it. All I know is that I'm going to do everything in my power to
bring it about. Beyond that, I can't count on anything. Quietism is the attitude of
people who say, "Let others do what I can't do." The doctrine I am presenting is the
very opposite of quietism, since it declares, "There is no reality except in action."
Moreover, it goes further, since it adds, "Man is nothing else than his plan; he exists
only to the extent that he fulfills himself; he is therefore nothing else than the
ensemble of his acts, nothing else than his life."
According to this, we can understand why our doctrine horrifies certain people.
Because often the only way they can bear their wretchedness is to think,
"Circumstances have been against me. What I've been and done doesn't show my true
worth. To be sure, I've had no great love, no great friendship, but that's because I
haven't met a man or woman who was worthy. The books I've written haven't been
very good because I haven't had the proper leisure. I haven't had children to devote
myself to because I didn't find a man with whom I could have spent my life. So there
remains within me, unused and quite viable, a host of propensities, inclinations,
possibilities, that one wouldn't guess from the mere series of things I've done."
Now, for the existentialist there is really no love other than one which manifests itself
in a person's being in love. There is no genius other than one which is expressed in
works of art; the genius of Proust is the sum of Proust's works; the genius of Racine is
his series of tragedies. Outside of that, there is nothing. Why say that Racine could
have written another tragedy, when he didn't write it? A man is involved in life,
leaves his impress on it, and outside of that there is nothing. To be sure, this may
seem a harsh thought to someone whose life hasn't been a success. But, on the other
hand, it prompts people to understand that reality alone is what counts, that dreams,
expectations, and hopes warrant no more than to define a man as a disappointed
dream, as miscarried hopes, as vain expectations. In other words, to define him
negatively and not positively. However, when we say, "You are nothing else than
your life," that does not imply that the artist will be judged solely on the basis of his
works of art; a thousand other things will contribute toward summing him up. What
we mean is that a man is nothing else than a series of undertakings, that he is the sum,
the organization, the ensemble of the relationships which make up these undertakings.
When all is said and done, what we are accused of, at bottom, is not our pessimism,
but an optimistic toughness. If people throw up to us our works of fiction in which we
write about people who are soft, weak, cowardly, and sometimes even downright bad,
it's not be. cause these people are soft, weak, cowardly, or bad; because if we were to
say, as Zola did, that they are that way because of heredity, the workings of
environment, society, because of biological or psychological determinism, people
would be reassured. They would say, "Well, that's what we're like, no one can do
anything about it." But when the existentialist writes about a coward, he says that this
coward is responsible for his cowardice. He's not like that because he has a cowardly
heart or lung or brain; he's not like that on account of his physiological make-up; but
he's like that because he has made himself a coward by his acts. There's no such thing
as a cowardly constitution; there are nervous constitutions; there is poor blood, as the
common people say, or strong constitutions. But the man whose blood is poor is not a
coward on that account, for what makes cowardice is the act of renouncing or
yielding. A constitution is not an act; the coward is defined on the basis of the acts he
performs. People feel, in a vague sort of way, that this coward we're talking about is
guilty of being a coward, and the thought frightens them. What people would like is
that a coward or a hero be born that way.
One of the complaints most frequently made about The Ways of Freedom* can be
summed up as follows: "After all, these people are so spineless, how are you going to
make heroes out of them?" This objection almost makes me laugh, for it assumes that
people are born heroes. That's what people really want to think. If you're born
cowardly, you may set your mind perfectly at rest; there's nothing you can do about it;
you'll be cowardly all your life, whatever you may do. If you're born a hero, you may
set your mind just as much at rest; you'll be a hero all your life; you'll drink like a
hero and eat like a hero. What the existentialist says is that the coward makes himself
cowardly, that the hero makes himself heroic. There's always a possibility for the
coward not to be cowardly any more and for the hero to stop being heroic. What
counts is total involvement; some one particular action or set of circumstances is not
total involvement.
*Les Chemins de 1a Liberté, M. Sartre's projected trilogy of novels, two of which,
L'Age de Raison (The Age of Reason) and Le Sursis (The Reprieve) have already
appeared.--Translator's note.Thus, I think we have answered a number of the charges
concerning existentialism. You see that it can not be taken for a philosophy of
quietism, since it defines man in terms of action; nor for a pessimistic description of
man--there is no doctrine more optimistic, since man's destiny is within himself; nor
for an attempt to discourage man from acting, since it tells him that the only hope is in
his acting and that action is the only thing that enables a man to live. Consequently,
we are dealing here with an ethics of action and involvement.
Nevertheless, on the basis of a few notions like these, we are still charged with
immuring man in his private subjectivity. There again we're very much
misunderstood. Subjectivity of the individual is indeed our point of departure, and
this for strictly philosophic reasons. Not because we are bourgeois, but because we
want a doctrine based on truth and not a lot of fine theories, full of hope but with no
real basis. There can be no other truth to take off from than this: I think; therefore, I
exist. There we have the absolute truth of consciousness becoming aware of itself.
Every theory which takes man out of the moment in which he becomes aware of
himself is, at its very beginning, a theory which confounds truth, for outside the
Cartesian cogito, all views are only probable, and a doctrine of probability which is
not bound to a truth dissolves into thin air. In order to describe the probable, you must
have a firm hold on the true. Therefore, before there can be any truth whatsoever,
there must be an absolute truth; and this one is simple and easily arrived at; it's on
everyone's doorstep; it's a matter of grasping it directly.
Secondly, this theory is the only one which gives man dignity, the only one which
does not reduce him to an object. The effect of all materialism is to treat all men,
including the one philosophizing, as objects, that is, as an ensemble of determined
reactions in no way distinguished from the ensemble of qualities and phenomena
which constitute a table or a chair or a stone. We definitely wish to establish the
human realm as an ensemble of values distinct from the material realm. But the
subjectivity that we have thus arrived at, and which we have claimed to be truth, is
not a strictly individual subjectivity, for we have demonstrated that one discovers in
the cogito not only himself, but others as well.
The philosophies of Descartes and Kant to the contrary, through the I think we reach
our own self in the presence of others, and the others are just as real to us as our own
self. Thus, the man who becomes aware of himself through the cogito also perceives
all others, and he perceives them as the condition of his own existence. He realizes
that he can not be anything (in the sense that we say that someone is witty or nasty or
jealous) unless others recognize it as such. In order to get any truth about myself, I
must have contact with another person. The other is indispensable to my own
existence, as well as to my knowledge about myself. This being so, in discovering my
inner being I discover the other person at the same time, like a freedom placed in
front of me which thinks and wills only for or against me. Hence, let us at once
announce the discovery of a world which we shall call intersubjectivity; this is the
world in which man decides what he is and what others are.
Besides, if it is impossible to find in every man some universal essence which would
be human nature, yet there does exist a universal human condition. It's not by chance
that today's thinkers speak more readily of man's condition than of his nature. By
condition they mean, more or less definitely, the a priori limits which outline man's
fundamental situation in the universe. Historical situations vary; a man may be born a
slave in a pagan society or a feudal lord or a proletarian. What does not vary is the
necessity for him to exist in the world, to be at work there, to be there in the midst of
other people, and to be mortal there. The limits are neither subjective nor objective,
or, rather, they have an objective and a subjective side. Objective because they are to
be found everywhere and are recognizable everywhere; subjective because they are
lived and are nothing if man does not live them, that is, freely determine his existence
with reference to them. And though the configurations may differ, at least none of
them are completely strange to me, because they all appear as attempts either to pass
beyond these limits or recede from them or deny them or adapt to them.
Consequently, every configuration, however individual it may be, has a universal
value.
Every configuration, even the Chinese, the Indian, or the Negro, can be understood by
a Westerner. "Can be understood" means that by virtue of a situation that he can
imagine, a European of 1945 can, in like manner, push himself to his limits and
reconstitute within himself the configuration of the Chinese, the Indian, or the
African. Every configuration has universality in the sense that every configuration
can be understood by every man. This does not at all mean that this configuration
defines man forever, but that it can be met with again. There is always a way to
understand the idiot, the child, the savage, the foreigner, provided one has the
necessary information.
In this sense we may say that there is a universality of man; but it is not given, it is
perpetually being made. I build the universal in choosing myself; I build it in
understanding the configuration of every other man, whatever age he might have
lived in. This absoluteness of choice does not do away with the relativeness of each
epoch. At heart, what existentialism shows is the connection between the absolute
character of free involvement, by virtue of which every man realizes himself in
realizing a type of mankind, an involvement always comprehensible in any age
whatsoever and by any person whosoever, and the relativeness of the cultural
ensemble which may result from such a choice; it must be stressed that the relativity
of Cartesianism and the absolute character of Cartesian involvement go together. In
this sense, you may, if you like, say that each of us performs an absolute act in
breathing, eating, sleeping, or behaving in any way whatever. There is no difference
between being free. like a configuration, like an existence which chooses its essence,
and being absolute. There is no difference between being an absolute temporarily
localized, that is, localized in history, and being universally comprehensible.
This does not entirely settle the objection to subjectivism. In fact, the objection still
takes several forms. First, there is the following: we are told, "So you're able to do
anything, no matter what!" This is expressed in various ways. First we are accused of
anarchy; then they say, "You're unable to pass judgment on others, because there's no
reason to prefer one configuration to another"; finally they tell us, "Everything is
arbitrary in this choosing of yours. You take something from one pocket and pretend
you're putting it into the other."
These three objections aren't very serious. Take the first objection. "You're able to do
anything, no matter what" is not to the point. In one sense choice is possible, but what
is not possible is not to choose. I can always choose, but I ought to know that if I do
not choose, I am still choosing. Though this may seem purely formal, it is highly
important for keeping fantasy and caprice within bounds. If it is true that in facing a
situation, for example, one in which, as a person capable of having sexual relations, of
having children, I am obliged to choose an attitude, and if I in any way assume
responsibility for a choice which, in involving myself, also involves all mankind, this
has nothing to do with caprice, even if no a priori value determines my choice.
If anybody thinks that he recognizes here Gide's theory of the arbitrary act, he fails to
see the enormous difference between this doctrine and Gide's. Gide does not know
what a situation is. He acts out of pure caprice. For us, on the contrary, man is in an
organized situation in which he himself is involved. Through his choice, he involves
all mankind, and he can not avoid making a choice: either he will remain chaste, or he
will marry without having children, or he will marry and have children; anyhow,
whatever he may do, it is impossible for him not to take full responsibility for the way
he handles this problem. Doubtless, he chooses without referring to preestablished
values, but it is unfair to accuse him of caprice. Instead, let us say that moral choice is
to be compared to the making of a work of art. And before going any further, let it be
said at once that we are not dealing here with an aesthetic ethics, because our
opponents are so dishonest that they even accuse us of that. The example I've chosen
is a comparison only.
Having said that, may I ask whether anyone has ever accused an artist who has
painted a picture of not having drawn his inspiration from rules set up a priori? Has
anyone ever asked, "What painting ought he to make?" It is clearly understood that
there is no definite painting to be made, that the artist is engaged in the making of his
painting, and that the painting to be made is precisely the painting he will have made.
It is clearly understood that there are no a priori aesthetic values, but that there are
values which appear subsequently in the coherence of the painting, in the
correspondence between what the artist intended and the result. Nobody can tell what
the painting of tomorrow will be like. Painting can be judged only after it has once
been made. What connection does that have with ethics? We are in the same creative
situation. We never say that a work of art is arbitrary. When we speak of a canvas of
Picasso, we never say that it is arbitrary; we understand quite well that he was making
himself what he is at the very time he was painting, that the ensemble of his work is
embodied in his life.
The same holds on the ethical plane. What art and ethics have in common is that we
have creation and invention in both cases. We can not decide a priori what there is to
be done. I think that I pointed that out quite sufficiently when I mentioned the case of
the student who came to see me, and who might have applied to all the ethical
systems, Kantian or otherwise, without getting any sort of guidance. He was obliged
to devise his law himself. Never let it be said by us that this man--who, taking
affection, individual action, and kind-heartedness toward a specific person as his
ethical first principle, chooses to remain with his mother, or who, preferring to make a
sacrifice, chooses to go to England--has made an arbitrary choice. Man makes
himself. He isn't ready made at the start. In choosing his ethics, he makes himself, and
force of circumstances is such that he can not abstain from choosing one. We define
man only in relationship to involvement. It is therefore absurd to charge us with
arbitrariness of choice.
In the second place, it is said that we are unable to pass judgment on others. In a way
this is true, and in another way, false. It is true in this sense, that, whenever a man
sanely and sincerely involves himself and chooses his configuration, it is impossible
for him to prefer another configuration, regardless of what his own may be in other
respects. It is true in this sense, that we do not believe in progress. Progress is
betterment. Man is always the same. The situation confronting him varies. Choice
always remains a choice in a situation. The problem has not changed since the time
one could choose between those for and those against slavery, for example, at the
time of the Civil War, and the present time, when one can side with the Maquis
Resistance Party, or with the Communists.
But, nevertheless, one can still pass judgment, for, as I have said, one makes a choice
in relationship to others. First, one can judge (and this is perhaps not a judgment of
value, but a logical judgment) that certain choices are based on error and others on
truth. If we have defined man's situation as a free choice, with no excuses and no
recourse, every man who takes refuge behind the excuse of his passions, every man
who sets up a determinism, is a dishonest man.
The objection may be raised, "But why mayn't he choose himself dishonestly?" I
reply that I am not obliged to pass moral judgment on him, but that I do define his
dishonesty as an error. One can not help considering the truth of the matter.
Dishonesty is obviously a falsehood because it belies the complete freedom of
involvement. On the same grounds, I maintain that there is also dishonesty if I choose
to state that certain values exist prior to me; it is self-contradictory for me to want
them and at the same state that they are imposed on me. Suppose someone says to me,
"What if I want to be dishonest?" I'll answer, "There's no reason for you not to be, but
I'm saying that that's what you are, and that the strictly coherent attitude is that of
honesty."
Besides, I can bring moral judgment to bear. When I declare that freedom in every
concrete circumstance can have no other aim than to want itself, if man has once
become aware that in his forlornness he imposes values, he can no longer want but
one thing, and that is freedom, as the basis of all values. That doesn't mean that he
wants it in the abstract. It means simply that the ultimate meaning of the acts of
honest men is the quest for freedom as such. A man who belongs to a communist or
revolutionary union wants concrete goals; these goals imply an abstract desire for
freedom; but this freedom is wanted in something concrete. We want freedom for
freedom's sake and in every particular circumstance. And in wanting freedom we
discover that it depends entirely on the freedom of others, and that the freedom of
others depends on ours. Of course, freedom as the definition of man does not depend
on others, but as soon as there is involvement, I am obliged to want others to have
freedom at the same time that I want my own freedom. I can take freedom as my goal
only if I take that of others as a goal as well. Consequently, when, in all honesty, I've
recognized that man is a being in whom existence precedes essence, that he is a free
being who, in various circumstances, can want only his freedom, I have at the same
time recognized that I can want only the freedom of others.
Therefore, in the name of this will for freedom, which freedom itself implies, I may
pass judgment on those who seek to hide from themselves the complete arbitrariness
and the complete freedom of their existence. Those who hide their complete freedom
from themselves out of a spirit of seriousness or by means of deterministic excuses, I
shall call cowards; those who try to show that their existence was necessary, when it
is the very contingency of man's appearance on earth, I shall call stinkers. But
cowards or stinkers can be judged only from a strictly unbiased point of view.
Therefore though the content of ethics is variable, a certain form of it is universal.
Kant says that freedom desires both itself and the freedom of others. Granted. But he
believes that the formal and the universal are enough to constitute an ethics. We, on
the other hand, think that principles which are too abstract run aground in trying to
decide action. Once again, take the case of the student. In the name of what, in the
name of what great moral maxim do you think he could have decided, in perfect
peace of mind, to abandon his mother or to stay with her? There is no way of judging.
The content is always concrete and thereby unforeseeable; there is always the element
of invention. The one thing that counts is knowing whether the inventing that has
been done, has been done in the name of freedom.
For example, let us look at the following two cases. You will see to what extent they
correspond, yet differ. Take The Mill on the Floss. We find a certain young girl,
Maggie Tulliver, who is an embodiment of the value of passion and who is aware of
it. She is in love with a young man, Stephen, who is engaged to an insignificant
young girl. This Maggie Tulliver, instead of heedlessly preferring her own happiness,
chooses, in the name of human solidarity, to sacrifice herself and give up the man she
loves. On the other hand, Sanseverina, in The Charterhouse of Parma, believing that
passion is man's true value, would say that a great love deserves sacrifices; that it is to
be preferred to the banality of the conjugal love that would tie Stephen to the young
ninny he had to marry. She would choose to sacrifice the girl and fulfill her
happiness; and, as Stendhal shows, she is even ready to sacrifice herself for the sake
of passion, if this life demands it. Here we are in the presence of two strictly opposed
moralities. I claim that they are much the same thing; in both cases what has been set
up as the goal is freedom.
You can imagine two highly similar attitudes: one girl prefers to renounce her love
out of resignation; another prefers to disregard the prior attachment of the man she
loves out of sexual desire. On the surface these two actions resemble those we've just
described. However, they are completely different. Sanseverina's attitude is much
nearer that of Maggie Tulliver, one of heedless rapacity.
Thus, you see that the second charge is true and, at the same time, false. One may
choose anything if it is on the grounds of free involvement.
The third objection is the following: "You take something from one pocket and put it
into the other. That is, fundamentally, values aren't serious, since you choose them."
My answer to this is that I'm quite vexed that that's the way it is; but if I've discarded
God the Father, there has to be someone to invent values. You've got to take things as
they are. Moreover, to say that we invent values means nothing else but this: life has
no meaning a priori. Before you come alive, life is nothing; it's up to you to give it a
meaning, and value is nothing else but the meaning that you choose. In that way, you
see, there is a possibility of creating a human community.
I've been reproached for asking whether existentialism is humanistic. It's been said,
"But you said in Nausea that the humanists were all wrong. You made fun of a certain
kind of humanist. Why come back to it now?" Actually, the word humanism has two
very different meanings. By humanism one can mean a theory which takes man as an
end and as a higher value. Humanism in this sense can be found in Cocteau's tale
Around the World in Eighty Hours when a character, because he is flying over some
mountains in an airplane, declares, "Man is simply amazing." That means that I, who
did not build the airplanes, shall personally benefit from these particular inventions,
and that I, as man, shall personally consider myself responsible for, and honored by,
acts of a few particular men. This would imply that we ascribe a value to man on the
basis of the highest deeds of certain men. This humanism is absurd, because only the
dog or the horse would be able to make such an over-all judgment about man, which
they are careful not to do, at least to my knowledge.
But it can not be granted that a man may make a judgment about man. Existentialism
spares him from any such judgment. The existentialist will never consider man as an
end because he is always in the making. Nor should we believe that there is a
mankind to which we might set up a cult in the manner of Auguste Comte. The cult of
mankind ends in the self-enclosed humanism of Comte, and, let it be said, of fascism.
This kind of humanism we can do without.
But there is another meaning of humanism. Fundamentally it is this: man is constantly
outside of himself; in projecting himself, in losing himself outside of himself, he
makes for man's existing; and, on the other hand, it is by pursuing transcendent goals
that he is able to exist; man, being this state of passing-beyond, and seizing upon
things only as they bear upon this passing-beyond, is at the heart, at the center of this
passing-beyond. There is no universe other than a human universe, the universe of
human subjectivity. This connection between transcendency, as a constituent element
of man--not in the sense that God is transcendent, but in the sense of passing beyond--
and subjectivity, in the sense that man is not closed in on himself but is always
present in a human universe, is what we call existentialism humanism. Humanism,
because we remind man that there is no law-maker other than himself, and that in his
forlornness he will decide by himself; because we point out that man will fulfill
himself as man, not in turning toward himself, but in seeking outside of himself a goal
which is just this liberation, just this particular fulfillment.
>From these few reflections it is evident that nothing is more unjust than the
objections that have been raised against us. Existentialism is nothing else than an
attempt to draw all the consequences of a coherent atheistic position. It isn't trying to
plunge man into despair at all. But if one calls every attitude of unbelief despair, like
the Christians, then the word is not being used in its original sense. Existentialism
isn't so atheistic that it wears itself out showing that God doesn't exist. Rather, it
declares that even if God did exist, that would change nothing. There you've got our
point of view. Not that we believe that God exists, but we think that the problem of
His existence is not the issue. In this sense existentialism is optimistic, a doctrine of
action, and it is plain dishonesty for Christians to make no distinction between their
own despair and ours and then to call us despairing.
From :
https://pdfs.semanticscholar.org/fee6/cc76e59e40e2d03736206e0ed647519221e4.pdf?_ga=2.261680974.2103805658.1591131576-956305731.1591131576